The Enduring Evolution of Logic (guest post by Thomas Ferguson & Graham Priest)


The following guest post* is by Thomas Ferguson and Graham Priest (both of CUNY) and appears here via a special arrangement with Oxford University Press and the OUP Blog, at which it is also posted.


alphabet evolution 3

The Enduring Evolution of Logic
by Thomas Ferguson and Graham Priest

Logic is a deep subject, at the core of much work in philosophy, mathematics, and computer science. In very general terms, it is the study of what (conclusions) follows from what (premises)—logical consequence—as in:

Premise: All men are mortal

Premise: Socrates is a man

Conclusion: So Socrates is mortal

The Early Modern philosopher, Immanuel Kant, held that Aristotle invented logic, and at his hands it was complete. There was nothing left to be done. As he says:

“Logic, by the way, has not gained much in content since Aristotle’s times and indeed it cannot, due to its nature… In present times there has been no famous logician, and we do not need any new inventions in logic, because it contains merely the form of thinking.”
— From the introduction to his lectures on logic

He was notoriously wrong.

In the development of Western logic, there have been three very significant phases interspersed with two periods of stasis—and even forgetfulness. (Logic in Eastern philosophy has its own story to tell.) The first was in Ancient Greece, where logic was developed quite differently by Aristotle and the Stoics. The second phase was at the hands of the great Medieval logicians, such as Jean Buridan and William of Ockham. They took up their Ancient heritage, but developed it in many new ways, with theories of suppositio (truth conditions), insolubilia (paradoxes), consequentia (logical consequence), and other things. The rise of Humanism in Europe had a profound effect. Scholasticism was swept away, and with it went all the great Medieval advances in logic. Indeed, it was only in the second half of the 20th Century that we have come to discover the many things that were lost. All that remained in the 18th Century was a somewhat stylized form of Aristotelian logic. That is what Kant knew, and that is why he believed that there had been no advances since Aristotle.

The third great period in the development of logic is the contemporary one. The ground for this was laid in the middle of the 19th century by algebraists, such as George Boole. But, driven by questions in the foundations of mathematics, a new canon of logic was invented by Gottlob Frege, taken over by Bertrand Russell, and then polished by some of the greatest mathematicians of the first half of the 20th century, such as David Hilbert and Kurt Gödel. The view that emerged came to be called classical logicsomewhat oddly, since it has nothing to do with Ancient Greece or Rome. Indeed, it is at odds with elements of both Aristotle’s logic and Stoic logic. At any rate, by the middle of the 20th Century it had become completely orthodox. It is now the account of logic that you will be taught if you take a first course in the subject in most places in the world.

However, this very orthodoxy can often produce a blindness akin to Kant’s. The way that logic is taught is usually ahistorical and somewhat dogmatic. This is what logic is; just learn the rules. It is as if Frege had brought down the tablets from Mount Sinai: the result is God-given, fixed, and unquestionable. No sense is provided of the fact that logic has been in a state of development for two and a half thousand years, driven by developments in philosophy, science, and mathematics—and now computer science.

Indeed, many of the most intriguing developments in logic for the last 50 years are in the area of non-classical logic. Non-classical logics are logics that attempt to repair various of the inadequacies perceived in classical logic—by adding expressive resources that it lacks, by developing new techniques of inference, or by accepting that classical logic has got some things just plain wrong. In the process, old certainties are disappearing, and the arguments generated in new debates give the whole area a sense of excitement that is rarely conveyed to a beginning student, or understood by philosophers not party to these debates.

What generated the third phase in the development of logic was its mathematization. Techniques of mathematics were applied to the analysis of logical consequence, to produce theories and results of a depth hithertofore unobtainable. For example, the work of Kurt Gödel and Alan Turing in the first half of the 20th century, established quite remarkable limitations on axiomatic and computational methods. But, for all its mathematical sophistication, the developments in logic were driven by deep philosophical issues, concerning truth, the nature of mathematics, meaning, computation, paradox, and other things. The progress in this third phase shows no sign, as yet, of abating. Where it will lead, no one, of course, knows. But one thing seems certain. Logic provides a theory, or set of theories, about what follows from what, and why. And like any theoretical inquiry, it has evolved, and will continue to do so. It will surely produce theories of greater depth, scope, subtlety, refinement—and maybe even truth.

Disputed Moral Issues - Mark Timmons - Oxford University Press
Subscribe
Notify of
guest

10 Comments
Oldest
Newest Most Voted
Inline Feedbacks
View all comments
Will Behun
Will Behun
7 years ago

I am the first one to admit that my understanding of logic sort of grinds to a halt in the late middle ages, which is a serious deficiency. On the other hand, from a paedagogical standpoint, just getting students to understand the most basic principles can be enough of a challenge without the more sophisticated issues raised by contemporary logic.

Tom
Tom
Reply to  Will Behun
7 years ago

(Important preferatory remark: I may be misjudging myself)

This is true. Students struggle to learn logic. But I’ve also found that as I’ve learned more and more logic, I’ve been able to get more and more across in a semester.

Tom
Tom
Reply to  Tom
7 years ago

Oh shoot! I should point out that I’m *not* Tom Ferguson. I’m a different Tom.

Edward
Edward
7 years ago

Nothing on hegel?

Tom
Tom
Reply to  Edward
7 years ago

Genuinely not meant as snarky: Hegel said things about logic?

Georg
Georg
Reply to  Tom
7 years ago

Yes. Hegel’s Science of Logic. Cf. e.g. https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/Science+of+Logic, and Priest’s writings.

Paulo Ernesto Canongia Long
Paulo Ernesto Canongia Long
7 years ago

Lógica
Premise: All men are mortal
Premise: Socrates is a man
Conclusion: So Socrates is mortal

Premise: Socrates is mortal
Premise: Socrates is a man
Conclusion: So all men are Socrates.

Fustbariclation
Fustbariclation
7 years ago

Where can one find a guide to Gödel logics?

An idiots guide, or a short article would be good.

Adrian Cabreja
Adrian Cabreja
Reply to  Fustbariclation
7 years ago

Gödel’s Proof by Ernest Nagel

Robert
Robert
5 years ago

There is No mention of early Greek logic from the Eleatic school of the great Parmenides, much earlier and more advanced/modern than Aristotle.

This led to Megaran logic and thereby influenced the Stoics.

*****

As regards modern logic, G. Cantor’s significance in introducing Set Theory cannot be overstated in revolutionizing both Logic and Set Theory.

Current Infinitary and even non compact logics as well as Modal logics could have been mentioned in this article.