Begin typing your search above and press return to search. Press Esc to cancel.

  • image/svg+xml Ello Ello

Daily Nous

news for & about the philosophy profession

Daily Nous

Primary Navigation

  • About
  • Comments Policy
  • Open, Live, Online Philosophy Events
  • Philosophy Comics
  • Value of Philosophy
  • Calls: Papers/Events/Grants/etc.
  • Non-Academic Hires
  • Supporters
  • Heap of Links
Home
Teaching

Service-Learning in Philosophy Courses


By
Justin Weinberg
.
January 21, 2022 at 9:17 am 37

“Moral problems, like global and local food insecurity, aren’t just abstract problems; they are practical problems with practical solutions. It’s important not just to present students with the problems, but also to empower them with real-world actions they can perform to help alleviate these problems.”

That’s Mylan Engel, professor of philosophy at Northern Illinois University, in an interview at Engaged Philosophy (previously).

Mylan Engel (right) and his Philosophy of Food students packing food at Feed My Starving Children (photo via Engaged Philosophy)

Professor Engel, who teaches courses in, among other things, animal ethics, environmental ethics, and philosophy of food, makes use of service-learning in his instruction. He says:

The students in my “Philosophy of Food” course are expected to complete at least 21 hours of community-engaged service during the course of the semester. Service activities include:

• Volunteering at Feed My Starving Children
• Planting seeds in NIU’s greenhouse
• Working in NIU’s Communiversity Garden
• Preparing and sharing a vegan dish at the end-of-the-semester Sustainable Supper

In addition to the above activities, which we all perform together as a class, students are expected to identify a food-related issue/problem they are passionate about and spend at least 5 hours working on a project designed to address that problem.

Students “gain a deeper understanding of and appreciation for the practical significance of philosophy. They also gain a sense of empowerment” from the work, Professor Engel says.

In this brief video, he and his students talk about the benefits of this kind of coursework:

You can learn more about the service-learning projects and lessons Professor Engel uses in the full interview.

The Engaged Philosophy website is a useful resource for those interested in bringing service learning and civic engagement into their courses, with information about various service learning projects, sample syllabi, other interviews, and more.

Do you make use of service-learning, civic engagement, or other hands-on projects in your philosophy courses? Let us know about them. Are you trying to figure out how to make use of these teaching tools for a particular philosophical subject? Let’s hear about it. Discussion welcome.

Categories Teaching
Tags civic engagementethicsmoral philosophyservice learningteachingvalue of philosophy

8 likes
Login
guest

guest

37 Comments
Oldest
Newest Most Voted
Inline Feedbacks
View all comments
Benjamin Yelle
Benjamin Yelle
1 year ago

A Northeastern University I teach a “Philosophy for Children” course where my students and I teach local elementary school kids philosophy through kids books (very much inspired by Thomas Wartenberg’s approach).

First iteration of the course was interrupted by Covid but (tentatively) planning/hoping to teach it this coming Fall.Report

8
Reply
Harald Karlsson
Harald Karlsson
1 year ago

This is a nice initiative, but I worry that it blurs the boundary between theory and practice. Every minute working in the soup kitchen, for example, is a minute not spent studying Mill and Kant. Sure, the all-thing-considered value of the soup kitchen might outweigh the purely intellectual value of intense study, however, let’s not conflate whether the soup kitchen *is* the studying.Report

21
Reply
SCM
SCM
Reply to  Harald Karlsson
1 year ago

It may be that working in a soup kitchen is not studying itself, but I take it that (part of) the point is that working in the soup kitchen can improve the quality of the students’s studying. To paraphrase Kipling and C.L.R. James, what can they know of philosophy, who only philosophy know?Report

10
Reply
Harald Karlsson
Harald Karlsson
Reply to  SCM
1 year ago

SCM, you say “but I take it that (part of) the point is that working in the soup kitchen can improve the quality of the students’s studying.” How so? I mean. To use an analogy: in the Karate Kid, the kid didn’t understand why Mr. Miagi was making him paint the fence. And then it turned out that the brush strokes were similar to tai-kwon-do — and so “aha, painting the fence was part of the study of tai-kwon-do.” But I’m not quite seeing it in the soup kitchen case. Putting soup in the bowl might very well be practice for when you have to take the visiting speaker out for dinner … but it doesn’t teach them Kant and Mill. Report

7
Reply
SCM
SCM
Reply to  Harald Karlsson
1 year ago

This isn’t really that hard. They can study Kant and Mill as much as they like. But they may not have a very deep appreciation for ethics if they don’t directly experience contexts that depart from their normal life.Report

7
Reply
Cathy Legg
Cathy Legg
Reply to  Harald Karlsson
1 year ago

Harald what is your definition of ‘studying’?Report

1
Reply
Harald Karlsson
Harald Karlsson
Reply to  Cathy Legg
1 year ago

I am glad you asked, Cathy. My definition of studying is a sober, close, careful, reading of the text. This has been the same definition of studying from Ancient Greece to the present day.Report

1
Reply
Haley Dutmer
Haley Dutmer
1 year ago

Inspiring work, Mylan!

I’m teaching Philosophy of Education this semester at Notre Dame. As part of the class my students are volunteering at a local community learning center.Report

14
Reply
David Wallace
David Wallace
1 year ago

A concern I have with this sort of component of a course (and it’s a concern, not a decisive reason not to do it) is that it’s probably quite hard to do it without requiring students to adopt some substantive conclusions about the subject matter of the course. Presumably it wouldn’t be okay to do a course on the ethics of abortion where students were required to spend 5 hours volunteering at an abortion clinic, or indeed 5 hours protesting outside an abortion clinic. I can see that you could have a more generalized ‘spend 5 hours volunteering for some cause you regard as good’, but you might have to work quite hard to reassure students that they weren’t going to be penalized for having particular views of what counts as a good cause.

(I don’t know to what extent Professor Engel’s service requirement accommodates students who radically disagree with his substantive views about food ethics; quite possibly they’re fully accommodated. This isn’t a particular comment on his course.)Report

32
Reply
Dallas H
Dallas H
Reply to  David Wallace
1 year ago

As someone who has previously taken multiple graduate seminars with Dr. Engel, I can attest to his openness to being challenged and disagreed with. In my experience, his evaluation has never reflected his position on the content, but the strength of arguments, clarity of writing, etc. Of course, you note that your point is not a particular comment on Engel’s course(s).
I do, however, think your concern stands: for courses that incorporate service components, students may fundamentally disagree with the positions being advocated by the course or the professor. To that point, I am glad that most of my past philosophy courses have not been structured in this way. But for the few that have, the experience of connecting philosophical ideas to practice was both formative and fulfilling. I suppose professors considering this course structure should, among other things, carefully consider the pros and cons of service learning components for the types of students in their program.Report

9
Reply
David Wallace
David Wallace
Reply to  Dallas H
1 year ago

Good to know, and as I say, I’d no reason to think otherwise (it’s a more general concern).Report

2
Reply
Rawls’ Ghost
Rawls’ Ghost
Reply to  David Wallace
1 year ago

Solution: only service learning courses that can be given a public reason justification are admissible!Report

5
Reply
Jason Brennan
Jason Brennan
1 year ago

I do something like this:

https://philosopherscocoon.typepad.com/blog/2019/05/teaching-ethics-to-business-students-the-ethics-project-jason-brennan.htmlReport

10
Reply
Madeline Martin-Seaver
Madeline Martin-Seaver
Reply to  Jason Brennan
1 year ago

FWIW, I appreciated that post a lot when it first went up and have started doing a similar project. Thanks for taking the time to write it up and share it with the profession.Report

3
Reply
Doris
Doris
1 year ago

Cornell has just launched a moral psychology minor — so far as I know, the first moral psychology minor (link below).

The minor’s engaged learning component is concentrated in a dedicated “capstone” course, which may address some of David’s concerns.

https://psychology.cornell.edu/-moral-psychology-minorReport

1
Reply
Alastair Norcross
Alastair Norcross
1 year ago

It’s a great course (I saw a presentation Mylan did on it a few years back). If you’re worried about students being made to do things that go against their principles, I presume that the requirements are advertised up front, so students whose principles preclude them from helping to alleviate food insecurity, help plants to grow, or cook vegan meals (oh, the horror!) can opt for different classes. Similarly, students whose principles preclude them from even considering arguments for or against the existence of a supernatural deity can choose not to take a philosophy of religion class, and students whose principles preclude them from being exposed to Darwinian theories of evolution can choose not to take an evolutionary biology class. As to the worry that time spent doing practical things, like packing meals for underprivileged people or planting seeds for plants to grow, is time not spent studying theory, that’s true. But so what? It’s not as if this class doesn’t also have plenty of time spent studying theory. Unless you think that every minute of every day should be spent studying theory, this “worry” seems totally irrelevant.Report

18
Reply
David Wallace
David Wallace
Reply to  Alastair Norcross
1 year ago

How far do you extend that? To borrow my earlier example, would it be okay for my class to require students to organize an anti-abortion protest, provided that the course prospectus makes clear that’s part of the requirements? Or, in your philosophy of religion example, is it okay if the class is required to take Holy Communion?Report

17
Reply
Barry Lam
Barry Lam
Reply to  David Wallace
1 year ago

Of course there are going to be substantive assumptions of value involved in the particular choice of engaged-learning. There are substantive assumptions of value involved in particular choices of theoretical learning. One professor teaches philosophy of religion using only texts in the Christian catholic tradition. One only teaches it from Buddhist traditions. The Thomist thinks its a complete disservice to what philosophy of religion ought to be that they’re talking about this or that conception of nirvana rather than the rationality of faith or certain a priori arguments for the existence of God. The students in one college only does service-learning based on Evangelical conceptions of the good. We argue about whether that course is better than the soup-kitchen couse on blogs. Isn’t that what have discretionary freedom over courses is about, and what makes US higher education great?Report

7
Reply
Dale Miller
Dale Miller
Reply to  Barry Lam
1 year ago

However, while a faculty member’s philosophical or religious stance will inevitably influence what gets taught in a traditional class, students still aren’t (or shouldn’t be) required to endorse that stance or act against their own stance to pass the class. They may have to consider arguments that come out of the Catholic tradition or even demonstrate an understanding of Catholicism, but they don’t have to claim to be Catholic or act in ways contrary to their faith (or lack thereof). A service learning class that required students to act in support of a controversial cause that they may in fact oppose would be quite different (at least at a state school). I’m not saying that Mylan Engel’s course has this issue, and I’m not sure how many actual philosophy service learning classes do, but I can see the problem in principle. When I was chair a colleague was thinking about such a class and I pointed out that unless they broadened the range of activities that students could engage in they might run into this problem.Report

7
Reply
Alastair Norcross
Alastair Norcross
Reply to  Dale Miller
1 year ago

I’m not seeing this as a matter of defensible principle (as opposed to whatever half-baked state law may be in force) Dale. What if a student’s own stance forbids them from considering certain arguments? I’m sure we both agree that would be a very silly stance to have, but that’s our substantive judgment about the stance itself. I also think if a student has a stance against helping to feed the needy or plant food, that would be a very silly stance. There is simply no content-neutral principle that can reasonably forbid requiring practical activities but not intellectual activities.Report

3
Reply
Dale Miller
Dale Miller
Reply to  Alastair Norcross
1 year ago

Sure, I think that there are some stances a student could have that a state university just doesn’t have to accommodate. If your religion precludes you from learning about viewpoints other than its own, then you just aren’t going to get a degree from a state school. But I think that can be true and yet it can also be true that there are a range of issues that universities should treat as matters of legitimate controversy and that getting credit in a class shouldn’t require taking a particular side in the controversy. That includes being required to affirm that a certain view is correct or doing practical work to promote one side. So for example, a service learning class in political science that gives students credit for working on a political campaign seems okay—but not if it requires working for a particular politician or a particular party. When it comes to working with a community group, say, there are some groups that are anodyne enough that having the opportunity tied to that specific group might be fine. There are others where that’s probably not true. If you’re going to give students ethics credit for working with a group that wants to restrict gun ownership, for instance, you probably have to offer the same credit for doing comparable work for the NRA.Report

5
Reply
Barry Lam
Barry Lam
Reply to  Dale Miller
1 year ago

I would hope that an instructor, service learning or ordinary learning, has the wisdom to grant exceptions to students who object to doing readings or assignments on moral, religious, or other grounds, or not to grant such exceptions, based on their expert pedagogical judgment. If they make a wrong call, well, we all fuck up in our jobs sometimes right?Report

3
Reply
Laura Grams
Laura Grams
Reply to  Barry Lam
1 year ago

Some of my state legislators are considering solving this problem preemptively by making it illegal for public schools to include a service learning component that is in any way affiliated with any group that does lobbying or takes any political stance. This would wipe out every service learning project my kids have ever been involved in in public school, as well as many of the ones at my institution, and they are about as anodyne and non-controversial as you please – or more to the point, engaging in those activities is probably less provocative than engaging intellectually with some of the texts you’ll have to read for the class. I mentioned this just to note that this is not an abstract discussion, but occurs in a context where government control over the options is sought by at least some elected officials. I have never known of a service learning course where either the course or a component within it was required of a student and no other options existed for fulfilling the same credits.Report

2
Reply
Alastair Norcross
Alastair Norcross
Reply to  David Wallace
1 year ago

If the course prospectus makes it clear that organizing a protest or taking communion is one of the requirements, I think that would be fine, as far as the objection that concerns making students do things against their principles goes. The only problem I can see is if this class is required for the student to fulfill their major requirements. It would also be unfortunate, if the only philosophy of religion class available had that requirement, even if philosophy of religion were not required for the major. I find it somewhat amusing that some of the people who will argue (correctly) for professors’ wide discretion in assigning material for students to study will balk at the idea of assigning other activities for the students to engage in. It’s as if there’s an assumption that students’ principles concerning permissible ways of engaging in practical activity are different in kind, and worthy of a different kind of deference, from their principles concerning permissible ways of engaging in intellectual activity. Which is, of course, absurd.Report

6
Reply
David Wallace
David Wallace
Reply to  Alastair Norcross
1 year ago

Why is it absurd?Report

6
Reply
J. Bogart
J. Bogart
Reply to  Alastair Norcross
1 year ago

A course offered by a state university in the US that required students to take communion would fail a legal challenge. Just like mandatory prayers.Report

3
Reply
Chris Surprenant
Chris Surprenant
1 year ago

Glad to see the success others have had with these important courses. I’ve had a slightly different experience that I wonder whether or not it happens frequently.

We developed a service-learning course at UNO where we partnered with the local jail to teach reentering people basic computer and job skills. The class our students were taking was focused on ethics and the criminal justice system, and they were the ones teaching the computer and job skills to folks about to be released. (It was all well done–they received proper training, we worked closely with the staff at the jail, etc.)

Anyway, my colleagues declared that what we were doing was “not philosophy” and refused to add the course to the catalogue or list it again as a special topics. Have any of you had similar problems with colleagues telling you that service or experiential learning courses are not philosophy and shouldn’t be offered?Report

7
Reply
Barry Lam
Barry Lam
Reply to  Chris Surprenant
1 year ago

Wow I’m sorry happened Chris. I don’t know how curricular governance works at your institution. Here, new courses have to go through a curricular committee for approval. So in principle, a faculty member can appeal their own department’s reservations about a course directly to such a committee. Short of that, there are ways of appealing to the Dean when particular faculty feel strongly about course content that is at odds with their department. We haven’t ever had this problem in philosophy but I know of other departments where this happens. In the end, there is always an interdisciplinary program that would be happy to have something like this if departments don’t cooperate.Report

2
Reply
Justin Kalef
Justin Kalef
1 year ago

Interesting. So what about this: I could teach a course about the importance of free inquiry and of toleration for dissent, and have the following service learning component: all students must publicly defend *two* people who are attacked for their (alleged) positions or comments on some hot-button issue dear to their hearts — one on each side of the issue. The students then have to submit explanations of what they did (and evidence that they in fact did it), and reflect on various difficulties they will have encountered in persuading people to be more open-minded.

In this case, the service work would not just be the following of some principle for which one has seen philosophical arguments: it would also require students to use their skills directly in arguing for the permissibility of someone’s holding and expressing certain views, and in responding to those who object.

Moreover, this work is clearly non-partisan (someone deeply invested in trans issues would have to argue against someone’s being cancelled for championing trans rights, and also against someone’s being cancelled for criticizing some tenet of held by trans advocates), and I think it should be clear that allowing for greater intellectual tolerance is a genuine social good. We are, after all, philosophers trying to promote the philosophical spirit. Moreover, this service learning project would promote intellectual courage, which, I think it should be agreed, is in relatively short supply in these intellectually conforming times.

In spite of these virtues of this proposed project, I have little doubt that others would object to it. They might say, for instance, that this entire service learning component is based on a Millian or Ira-Glasser-style civil libertarian position that some philosophers reject. But I can acknowledge that this is true, in just the way that some philosophers reject the moral superiority of veganism or the existence of a duty to help the needy, and say that such disagreement doesn’t raise a problem for my proposed service learning component any more than the existence of other disagreement raises a problem for projects that require feeding the homeless or learning to cook vegan meals.

Does that suffice? Or do the worries persist?Report

5
Reply
Chris Surprenant
Chris Surprenant
Reply to  Justin Kalef
1 year ago

Justin, this seems like a very thoughtful and valuable exercise, but I’m not sure if it would count towards what many universities are identifying as “experiential learning.” That’s what seems to make philosophy somewhat odd here because by doing philosophy *in the classroom* or *through assignments* that *is* experiential learning, at least in philosophy.

In the case of our criminal justice ethics class, we thought it was important for the students to be able to connect with the people who are sitting in our jails right now. My colleagues were right in that teaching these individuals computer skills or jobs skills is distinctly not philosophy, but my position was (and still is) that doing philosophy well means having as much relevant empirical knowledge as possible that is relevant to the issue being discussed. So our “experiential learning” component allowed them to learn something — albeit not learning philosophy directly — through their non-philosophy interaction with the people in the jail. (But, again, I can see the point my colleagues were making about those hours not being philosophy.)

But if what we were doing here in New Orleans is not the kind of experiential learning we’re going to support in philosophy departments, it’s not entirely clear to me how philosophy can contribute to experiential learning in ways that our universities are going to count. What you’re suggesting, quite clearly, is experiential learning, but I imagine those types of exercises are already being done in many philosophy classes, and it is certainly not what people think of when they think of experiential learning.

One solution is that we can engage in a re-education project around what experiential learning is and why some disciplines, by their very nature, are doing experiential learning already. (That is, of course, why the sciences have lab classes.) But I’m not confident that project is likely to be successful, especially in fields like philosophy. Beyond that, we’re left doing the type of thing that I was doing in New Orleans and that others have suggested on here, but we’re likely to run into the objections that these projects are explicitly “not philosophy.”Report

4
Reply
Justin Kalef
Justin Kalef
Reply to  Chris Surprenant
1 year ago

Thanks, Chris. But I don’t yet see the parallel.

You say that “some disciplines, by their very nature, are doing experiential learning already. (That is, of course, why the sciences have lab classes.)”

Students in lab classes go beyond reading or hearing about the scientific facts and theories. They take part in the scientific work that generates those facts and theories. Rather than learning the results of the work of scientists, they themselves become scientists.

But I don’t yet see how teaching computing and job skills to prisoners helps ethics students experience what it’s like to work as a philosopher by generating or assessing philosophical theories or figuring out what they entail.Report

1
Reply
Chris Surprenant
Chris Surprenant
Reply to  Justin Kalef
1 year ago

Justin, that wasn’t the parallel I was drawing connections between. I was drawing a parallel between a chemistry lab and your example of what could be done in a philosophy class. I was then suggesting that both of these things should count as experiential learning, but would not count at the vast majority of colleges and universities given how “experiential learning” is defined.

So, that puts us in philosophy in a weird position, especially at schools that are trying to emphasize experiential learning. Do we try to convince the relevant administrators that what many faculty members are doing in philosophy should count as experiential learning? I don’t think that’s a winning strategy.

If not, then the question is a substantive one about whether these things that normally are considered to be service learning and “not philosophy,” and then a second question as to whether or not these “not philosophy” things can enhance a philosophy class in substantive and important ways.

In my specific example, I’m very sympathetic to the claim that teaching computing and job skills isn’t philosophy (since it’s not). But I’m also sympathetic to the position that it’s important for people to have certain experiences if they’re going to do philosophy well, especially when they’re thinking about difficult issues in social or political philosophy. In our case, we thought it would be very difficult, if not impossible, to think carefully about ethical issues related to the criminal justice system without having an opportunity to interact meaningfully with folks in our jails. This is a piece that most people working in criminal justice issues on the theoretical side simply don’t have.Report

2
Reply
Justin Kalef
Justin Kalef
Reply to  Chris Surprenant
1 year ago

Ah, I see! Thanks.

But then I think the question of bias becomes more important. Those who invest time working personally with prisoners who struggle to rehabilitate themselves will presumably come to see the prisoners more sympathetically. But those who instead spend time working with the victims of crimes as they try to put their lives together would presumably come to hold quite different sympathies, especially if their lives were seriously derailed by a convicted criminal on parole, and so on.Report

1
Reply
Dale Miller
Dale Miller
Reply to  Chris Surprenant
1 year ago

Something similar is true of “undergraduate research.” It’s easy to conclude that not many philosophy departments are participating in undergraduate research. On reflection, though, I think that they all are, and heavily so. If students are writing papers, well, that’s what research looks like in philosophy. And they always have the chance of hitting upon something novel that makes an interesting contribution.Report

1
Reply
Chris Surprenant
Chris Surprenant
Reply to  Dale Miller
1 year ago

That seems right to me, but part of our problem is that, at many universities, the only “research” that counts is the type that brings in dollars that the university can deduct overhead expenses from.Report

0
Reply
ajkreider
ajkreider
1 year ago

I’m open to the idea that such service deepens students’ understanding of the importance of philosophy, or of the philosophical ideas themselves (I get asked to add it to my courses every year) – but is there any ed data that backs this up?

I think there’s lots of service learning that does actually enhance the learning – like having the students teach others. But that is hard to do with intro level philosophy students, (and maybe a bit irresponsible? Are they going to talk to middle-schoolers about the problem of evil?)

In this case, what is learned? Not that “People who don’t have access to healthy food should have access to healthy food, and we should do something about that.” I mean, how much philosophy do you need to arrive at that claim? (Hopefully, none).

I’m all for service requirements for college high school students – even as part of a course. Volunteerism is good (even when it’s not fully voluntary). Not sure about the “learning” bit, as it relates to philosophy.Report

5
Reply
Lu Chen
Lu Chen
1 year ago

I imagine this sort of courses would have been a challenge for me because I am miserable at anything that requires practical skills (which was why I went for the most armchairing discipline). Not an objection to it — maybe it is as justified as requiring all physics students to do experiments…Report

0
Reply
Paid Advertisements

Recent Comments

Julia Staffel on APA Election Results

This was just coincidence. I didn't even realize my colleagues were running for election when I agreed. And we don't get any special credit from

Peter Davis on Rejection Rates Should Not Be a Measure of Journal Quality (guest post)

At the other end of the hierarchy are those journals with abnormally low rejection rates. In many cases this is commercially motivated as a number […]

Walter Horn on Faculty at Rhodes College Urge Cancellation of Online Talk by Peter Singer (updated)

My problem with Singer is that, based on a Nozick review (that I disagreed with) in the NY Times over 40 years ago of a […]

Dale Miller on Rejection Rates Should Not Be a Measure of Journal Quality (guest post)

I suppose that I was drawing on my own experience as an editor. (I edited Utilitas for 6 years.) I had an annual page budget […]

Paul Moore-Bridger on Calls for Papers / Grants / Etc.

Association of Philosophy Teachers (APT) inaugural annual conference, June 26th, Birmingham (UK). https://bpa.ac.uk/association-of-philosophy-teachers/

Walter Horn on Rejection Rates Should Not Be a Measure of Journal Quality (guest post)

FWIW, I'm not terribly surprised to hear that rejection rates are higher at philosophy journals than at journals covering other disciplines. I don't love this

Matt L on Rejection Rates Should Not Be a Measure of Journal Quality (guest post)

It's worth noting that, with law review submissions to US (*) law reviews, they are normally not peer reviewed (**), but rather reviewed by current […]

Gilbert Plumer on Calls for Papers / Grants / Etc.

CFP: Association for Informal Logic and Critical Thinking Essay Prize ($700). Submission deadline: September 1, 2023. https://ailact.files.wordpress.com/2023/05/ailact-essay-prize-2023-cfp.pdf

Mark van Roojen on Rejection Rates Should Not Be a Measure of Journal Quality (guest post)

Space constraints apply to online only journals as well as there are costs associated with publishing papers.

Felipe De Brigard on Rejection Rates Should Not Be a Measure of Journal Quality (guest post)

Thank you both for these responses. And thank you for this important work!

Toby Handfield on Rejection Rates Should Not Be a Measure of Journal Quality (guest post)

Further to Kevin's reply: if you tried to capture this idea within the narrow constraints of our model, you might represent it as a reduction […]

Kevin Zollman on Rejection Rates Should Not Be a Measure of Journal Quality (guest post)

I'm not sure I follow. If a journal cannot publish more than p papers, why does that entail that the journal will publish exactly […]

Subscribe

Archives

Paid Advertisements
Paid Advertisements

Heap of Links

  • “Why does so much of professional philosophy today seem so boring?” “Who’s an underrated philosopher that we should be reading more?” “What’s the most common topic you see crossing the desk of the [Journal of Controversial Ideas]?”? -- Tyler Cowen (GMU) asks Peter Singer some questions
  • “Irrationalist narratives” from psychology and behavioral economics have contributed to a disastrous loss in “epistemic empathy” -- but those narratives are highly questionable, argues Kevin Dorst (MIT), whose blog has a new home on Substack
  • “Computer says no” -- when AI's "black boxes" are used in ways that affect us, "we don't know the reason something’s happened, we can’t argue back, we can’t challenge, and so we enter the Kafkaesque realm of the absurd," says Alexis Papazoglou
  • “The people who find immoral jokes to be less funny because they are immoral are not in good positions to judge how funny immoral jokes are! You wouldn’t let someone averse to sweets judge a cake competition, would you?” -- Connor Kianpour (Colorado) defends strong comic immoralism
  • A philosophy student became an investment banker who became a collector of rare philosophy books -- Michael Walsh has donated his collection, which includes a first edition of Hume's Treatise and other gems, to the University of Toronto
  • “They provide us with a relatively recent, further perspective beyond continental philosophy from which to understand and critique the dominant approach in Anglophone philosophy.” -- American women philosophers in the speculative tradition in the first half of the 20th Century
  • “The most useful, freely accessible Classics tools online” -- a list of 100 open-access websites and resources curated by the team at Antigone
  • “Kant’s antinomies, properly digested, only require you to step back from the whole affair, to quit trying to find dogmatic solutions to metaphysical problems… But how do you step back, when everything seems to bring you to a similar impasse?” -- and Justin Smith-Ruiu does mean everything: flying, disability, air conditioning, almonds...
  • “All these different technical hacks are really motivated by exploiting a philosophical principle of computation of meta code” -- an interview with Scott Shapiro (Yale), whose new book is on hacking and hackers: "It's like to understand God, you've got to understand the people who made him"
  • Do philosophers and economists tend to agree on how much less future benefits and harms should matter compared to present benefits and harms? -- yes, "although on the basis of very different intellectual arguments"
  • “I’ve always thought of science, and especially scientific modeling, as fundamentally value-laden enterprises. But I’m really starting to feel like philosophers of science have fallen behind the curve on this” -- Eric Winsberg (South Florida) is interviewed at "What Is It Like To Be A Philosopher?"
  • “The point is not to reject new technology but to help students retain the upper hand in their relationship with it” -- why some profs, including philosopher David Peña-Guzmán (SFSU) are teaching low-tech, screen-free courses
  • “If one person does it, it’s not cancel culture.” “But if it’s okay for one person to do it, why isn’t it okay for a very large number of people to do it?” -- a book on free speech is reviewed, in dialogue format, by Brad Skow (MIT)
  • What do you wish you had known about doing a PhD in philosophy? -- 12 philosophy graduate students answer the question on the latest episode of The Philosopher's Nest
  • “Improved AIs pose an existential threat to their unimproved originals in the same manner that smarter-than-human AIs pose an existential threat to humans” -- Peter Salib (Houston) on why AIs will not "want" to self-improve, and so are in an important way less dangerous (via MR)
  • “Lurking in the standard position, which uniformly treats clarity as the effect [of successful] analysis, is a possible equivocation about what is fundamentally achieved” -- Eric Schliesser (Amsterdam) seeks clarity on the varieties of clarity philosophers have cared about
  • “Because of the growth and further intensification of animal production, humans inflict more suffering on animals today than they did in 1975” but the trends since then are “not all negative” -- Peter Singer (Princeton) reflects on the treatment of animals, 50 years after his first article on the subject was published
  • “I am now so convinced of the magic of teaching philosophy outside that I have no intention of going back inside, and I think others should try it” -- Ryan J. Johnson (Elon) with the case for taking your courses outside
  • “Four basic assumptions prevalent among UFO researchers and enthusiasts, as well as the general public that… deserve some prodding” -- outer space meets logical space in a philosophical look at how the "UFO community" operates, from Michael Glawson
  • Publish or perish: high school edition -- some high schoolers (whose parents can afford it) are producing "published" "research" to get into college (via Andy Lamey)
  • “Phenomenal realism seems so obviously plausible [but] it has so little going for it apart from its obviousness” -- this makes it an especially vulnerable thesis, argues Daniel Pallies (Lingnan) at his new blog
  • “To be an addict is to be vulnerable to what I call the ‘bear-trap model of punishment'” -- T. Virgil Murthy (CMU) interviewed about addiction and being an alcoholic philosopher when "alcohol is everywhere in the philosophy world"
  • Analytic and Continental philosophy had this in common: they were “obsessed with language” -- Crispin Sartwell (Dickinson) on the linguistic turn and the "turn away from the linguistic turn"
  • What the AI image generator Midjourney “thinks” professors look like -- by discipline
  • “As a student, the assumption I’ve encountered among authority figures is that if an essay is written with the help of ChatGPT, there will be some sort of evidence” -- “In reality, it’s very easy to use AI to do the lion’s share of the thinking while still submitting work that looks like your own”
  • “Abstract objects are objects that can’t enter into causal relations. If you believe in them, you must suppose that reality divides into two radically different realms” -- an interview with Peter van Inwagen (Notre Dame) at 3:16AM
  • “We need be very cautious about inferring what is rational to think now from what was a rational [epistemic] policy to have adopted” -- an epistemic puzzle from Alex Pruss (Baylor)
  • After Daisy Dixon got a job in philosophy, she tweeted a meme with images of herself and Hume in celebration. And then people were awful -- she recounts the story and its lessons at The Philosophers' Cocoon
  • “Gone is the idea of a totemic strand of DNA that extends six feet when uncoiled and stretched out in a straight line. Now, the rebooted reference resembles a corn maze, with alternative paths and side trails” -- our picture of the human genetic code just got a massive update
  • “Since anthropomorphism will always be part of how we see the world, we should design and regulate chatbots and other technologies in ways that minimize, if not eliminate, dishonest anthropomorphism” -- Evan Selinger (RIT) on an increasingly urgent problem

∙   2023 © Daily Nous   ∙
wpDiscuz
37
0
Discussion welcome. Click to comment.x
()
x
| Reply